Wednesday 29 May 2013

Director of Public Prosecutions (Cth) v Keating [2013] HCA 20

Case Note: Director of Public Prosecutions (Cth) v Keating [2013] HCA 20

The case of Director of Public Prosecutions (Cth) v Keating [2013] HCA 20 concerns the construction of s 4.3(b) of the Criminal Code 1995 (Cth) ("the Code") with regard to retrospective legislation, and the elements of offences relating to social security fraud under s 135.2 of the Code. The decision is also important for the way in which it treats provisions in other statutes that are meant to operate with the Code offences.

Facts

The defendant, Keating, was charged under the the Code, s 135.2(1), for failing to report increases in her income during the period she was receiving the Parent Payment Single (more commonly known as the Single Parent Pension, the payment received by single parents to assist in caring for their children): at [2]. Section 135.2(1) makes it an offence for a person to engage in conduct that involves deriving a financial benefit from the Commonwealth (physical element), and they know, or believe, they are not eligible to receive that advantage (mental element).

The case also concerned the Social Security (Administration) Act 1999 (Cth) (“the Administration Act”), s 66A, which was inserted by Social Security and Other Legislation Amendment (Miscellaneous Measures) Act 2011 (Cth) (“the Amendment Act”) to overcome the decision in Poniatowska v Director of Public Prosecutions (Cth) (2010) 107 SASR 578 (upheld by the High Court in Commonwealth Director of Public Prosecutions v Poniatowska (2011) 244 CLR 408; [2011] HCA 43), where the Full Court of the Supreme Court of South Australia decided, “the use of the expression "engages in conduct" in s 135.2(1)(a) did not overcome the requirement that the conduct charged must be the omission of an act that a person is under a legal duty to perform”: at [3], citing Poniatowska at 584. Section 66A purports to impose just such a legal duty by requiring a person in receipt of a social security payment to inform the Department (“Centrelink”) within 14 days after an “event or change or circumstances occurs that might affect the payment of that social security payment”. The Amendment Act, Sch 1, Item 3 provides that s 66A, "applies in relation to an event or change of circumstances that occurs on or after 20 March 2000". The charged offences were committed between May 2007 and September 2009: at [6].

The Case

The Commonwealth Director of Public Prosecutions (“CDPP”) contended that by reason of s 66A of the Administration Act, Keating was under a legal duty to inform Centrelink of her change in financial position. As she did not, s 4.3(b) of the Code was engaged: at [7]. Section 4.3(b) states, “An omission to perform an act can only be a physical element if: (b) the law creating the offence impliedly provides that the offence is committed by an omission to perform an act that by law there is a duty to perform.” (emphasis added).

Keating challenged the application of s 66A to her case on the grounds that s 135.2(1) requires the person be subject to the duty at the time of the omission: at [8]. Alternately, she contended that the retroactive function of s 66A was “a usurpation of or interference with the judicial power of the Commonwealth contrary to the separation of powers for which the Constitution provides”: at [8]. Both arguments rested on the fact that the provisions imposing the duty did not exist at the time she committed the omissions and therefore she should not be held liable.

The CDPP also alleged, in the alternative, that Keating failed to comply with “information notices” under the social security law, by not providing the correct financial information to the Department: at [9]. These notices are those issued to recipients of social security payments, relevantly here, requiring recipients to notify Centrelink of changes in their financial status. Under s 74(1) of the Administration Act it is an offence for a person not to comply with such a notice. Keating disputed that s 74 imposes such a duty for the purposes of liability under the Code: at [9].

The “Information Notices”

Keating was firstly issued a notice under s 67(2) of the Administration Act when her claim for the PPS was granted, and further notices under s 68(2) at various intervals: at [17]-[30]. Each notice required, “the person to inform the Department [Centrelink] if a specified event or change of circumstances occurs, or if the recipient becomes aware that a specified event or change of circumstances is likely to occur”: at [13].

Keating argued that an act required by an information notice is not “an act” under s 4.3(b) of the Code because:
  1. “[A] legal duty to act must be certain and it is unclear when the duty under an information notice arises and when it ceases”;
  2.  “[T]he duty is "qualified" in that it does not apply to the extent that a person is incapable of complying with the notice, and does not apply to a person who has a reasonable excuse for non-compliance”; and,
  3. “The creation of the lesser offence under the Administration Act for a failure to comply with an information notice is inconsistent with the same conduct attracting criminal responsibility for the more serious offence under the Code.” (at [34]).

In answer to the first argument, the court (French CJ, Hayne, Crennan, Kiefel, Bell and Keane JJ) held that the duty was not unclear, but was rather a factual question depending upon the content of the notices: at [37]. In addressing the second and third arguments it held that, simply because the offence under s 74(1) of the Administration Act was lesser than that under s 135.2(1) of the Code, it did not amount to an inconsistency between the statutes. Although an offence under s 74(1) may constitute an element under s 135.2(1), the two offences contain different elements and thus, one cannot “subvert” the other: at [36]. It did however note that a conviction under s 135.2(1) may bar a subsequent prosecution under s 74(1): see Pearce v The Queen (1998) 194 CLR 610 at 616-620; [1998] HCA 57 at [18]-[28]. Therefore, the information notices were capable of creating a legal duty for the purposes of s 4.3(b); a failure to comply with information notices does constitute an omission under s 135.2(1): at [39].

Section 66A

The court held that the CDPP’s construction of s 66A of the Administration Act created “a statutory fiction with the effect of attaching criminal liability to the defendant for her failure to advise the Department of an event within 14 days of its occurrence”: at [46]. While the Parliament is within its power to impose such liability, to do so “[a] clear statement of legislative intention is required”: at [47]. To this end, the CDPP pointed to the remedial purposes of the Amendment Act and the Explanatory Memorandum: at [40]-[41]. The CDPP further submitted that “the usual criticism” of retrospective penal legislation did not apply here as all relevant people would have been aware that they were under an obligation to inform “the Department of the specified events and changes of circumstances listed in the notices given to them by Centrelink”: at [42]. But the issue was not the construction of s 66A, rather the interpretation of ss 4.3 and 135.2 of the Code, which was not the subject of the Amendment Act: at [47]. The court focused on the tense used in s 4.3(b) – “there is a duty to perform.” Their Honours concluded, “Criminal responsibility under s 4.3 is confined to the failure to do a thing that at the time of the failure the law requires the person to do. The obligation is coincident with the failure to discharge it”: at [49] (emphasis added). In other words, the court looked to the traditional requirement of the criminal law that the physical element coincide with the requisite mental element. Unless both can be said to be present at the same time, then no offence can be committed. Therefore, the court held that s 66A did not create a legal duty at the time of the charged offences, and due to facts in issue regarding the receipt of these notices, further consideration of whether the duty had arisen was remitted to the Victorian Magistrates’ Court for determination: at [38], [52].

Conclusion

The decision raises two important points with regard to an offence under s 135.2 of the Code. The first is that the legal duty imposed by s 74(1) of the Administration Act will be sufficient to create a legal duty for the purposes of s 135.2(1). The second is that s 66A of the Administration Act must, in this case, be regarded as a nullity. The court has very strictly applied the rule of statutory interpretation that penal statutes, especially retrospective ones, will be construed narrowly. It is arguable in this case that the court applied the rule in contradistinction to the will of parliament, as the very reasoning behind the insertion of s 66A was to address the exact circumstance concerning Keating. Indeed, there was no doubt that the Parliament had indicated clearly that s 66A was to have retrospective operation. In this sense a clear legislative intention had been expressed, and the section should have been interpreted in accordance with the Acts Interpretation Act 1901 (Cth) which requires courts adopt a purposive approach to interpretation. Thus the presumption against retrospectivity was rebutted: see Maxwell v Murphy (1957) 96 CLR 261 at 267; R vKidman (1915) 20 CLR 425 at 451; DC Pearce and RS Geddes, Statutory Interpretation in Australia (7th ed, 2011) at [10.12]. Where it seemingly failed was that it was expressed in a different statute from the Code. However, it is axiomatic to suggest that these provisions are intended to function as a legislative scheme. A legislative scheme is where a number of statutes form a scheme, and thus are meant to work together to fulfil their legislative purpose. The principles applicable to the interpretation of statutes in schemes are well-known: Sweeney v Fitzhardinge (1906) 4 CLR 716 at 726; DC Pearce and RS Geddes, Statutory Interpretation in Australia (7th ed, 2011) at [3.39]. In Commr of Stamp Duties v Permanent Trustee Co Ltd (1987) 9 NSWLR 719 at 723-724, Kirby P (as he then was) stated that the preferred construction of statutes with provisions clearly intended to work together was to interpret them harmoniously with one another: “We should presume that Parliament intended its legislation to operate rationally, efficiently and justly, together.” This approach was applied by Kirby P in Abdi v Release on Licence Board (1987) 10 NSWLR 294 at 295; 31 A Crim R 436 at 437 in the criminal context. It should be noted that there were no citations in the judgment here of any of the cases Pearce and Geddes cite as being emblematic of this approach.

It is argued in light of the apparent legislative scheme here, the court should have construed the s 4.3(b) with s 66A, not simply cast the latter to one side. Were this other than retrospective penal legislation, the court may have held otherwise and adopted a harmonious construction. But, as this decision illustrates, where the parliament insists on passing legislation so offensive to common law principles, it should not be surprising that the courts will use all the interpretive tools at their disposal to redress it. In future, the Parliament will need to ensure that it is mindful of the legal background against which its laws will operate; and the foundations on which the common law and the rules of interpretation are based.

Monday 27 May 2013

Aristocrat Technologies Australia Pty Ltd v Global Gaming Supplies Pty Ltd; Aristocrat Technologies Australia Pty Ltd v Allam [2013] HCA 21



The case of Aristocrat Technologies Australia Pty Ltd v Global Gaming Supplies Pty Ltd; Aristocrat Technologies Australia Pty Ltd v Allam [2013] HCA 21 concerns the application of s 97 “The tendency rule” of the Evidence Act 1995 (Cth) in the context of the civil law. Though brief, the judgement does illustrate the construction given to the section, and the implications of such reasoning on the interpretation of the Evidence Act as a whole.

Facts

The respondents, Anthony Andrews and Francis Cragen, sole directors and shareholders of Global Gaming Supplies Pty Ltd (“Global”) and Impact Gaming Pty Ltd (“Impact”), contracted Riad Allam, principal of Tonita Enterprise Pty Ltd (“Tonita”) to refurbish electronic gaming machines to sell to foreign markets.

The software installed on these machines by Allam though, were pirated copies of computer programs, containing artwork and compliance plates, that were the intellectual property of Aristocrat Technologies Pty Ltd (“Aristocrat”) and others, the applicants.

The applicants brought a claim against the respondents in the Federal Court of Australia under ss 36 and 38 of the Copyright Act 1968 (Cth) (“the Act”) for infringing their intellectual property in the software.

Section 36 of the Act concerns the doing of an act that infringes the intellectual property of another. Section 38 concerns dealing with the counterfeit copies knowing, or ought reasonably knowing, that the “that the making of the article constituted an infringement of the copyright”: s 38(1)(b).

As the High Court summarised it, “The essence of the applicants' case... was that the Global and Impact respondents were in a joint venture together "to counterfeit and sell, principally in South America, second hand gaming machines assembled in Australia using pirated copies of materials in which the applicants hold the copyright."” (at [7])

Aristocrat alleged 54 transactions in which the respondents exported counterfeit gaming machines, and while the trial judge was satisfied 11 of these contained counterfeit components, it was not possible to identify which components of the gaming machines were counterfeit, and which were not: at [8].

The evidence relied upon by the applicants to link Global and Impact to the infringing acts under s 38 were a series of emails between all of the respondents and potential customers between November 2004 and November 2005.

The trial judge identified “five essential propositions” in making a finding that the respondents were liable under the Act (at [9]):

  1. The Tonita respondents (specifically Mr Allam) had copied the applicants' game software onto blank EPROMs (erasable programmable read only memory chips). (s 36)
  2. The Tonita respondents (specifically Mr Allam) manufactured counterfeit compliance plates. (s 36)
  3. Mr Andrews and Mr Cragen were aware that Mr Allam was copying the applicants' game software onto blank EPROMs. (s 38)
  4. Mr Andrews and Mr Cragen were aware that Mr Allam was manufacturing counterfeit compliance plates for export to foreign markets. (s 38)
  5. Mr Andrews and Mr Cragen sent, or were aware that the joint venture had sent, original and digital artwork to South America for the purpose of having it copied. (s 38)
The emails consisted of a variety of conversations to the effect that each of the respondents intended and/or knew they were involved in infringing the copyright of the applicants via the copying and use of artwork and the installation of these in the refurbished gaming machines: at [16]-[19].

Crucially, the emails had been admitted under s 136 of the Evidence Act 1995 (Cth) limiting their admissibility to the case against particular respondents: at [13]. But after the close of evidence and at the time for final submissions, the applicants successfully applied for a variation of that ruling to allow the email evidence to be admissible against all of the respondents: at [13]. The applicants were successful in their claim, and the respondents appealed to the Full Federal Court.

The Full Federal Court Case

The Full Federal Court examined the email evidence and concluded that at best it was admissible as tendency evidence against Global and Impact. The reason for this was that the emails were essential to the applicants establishing the requirement of knowledge under s 38 of the Act, but that “The significant emails tendered did not relate to the alleged infringing transactions. They appeared to have been tendered to discredit witnesses and/or prove the existence of a joint venture. ” (at [28]) However, the trial judge treated them as going beyond this use. As the High Court said, “The only way the primary judge could have made the necessary connection between the infringing transactions and the joint venture was to draw an inference, based on the content of the emails, that the respondents had the tendency to act in a particular way, which involved dealing with articles, the making of which infringed copyright of the applicants, with the requisite knowledge.” (at [28])

As the evidence went to tendency, s 97 of the Evidence Act 1995 (Cth) was relevant, which states that such evidence is not admissible to prove tendency unless the party seeking to adduce the evidence gave reasonable notice to the other party or parties that they intend to do so, and the court thinks it will have significant probative value, either alone or with other evidence. As the trial judge did not comply with the requirements under s 97, the evidence was inadmissible against the respondents, and therefore the connection between the emails and the infringements could not be sustained: at [32].

The Full Court went onto note that even accepting a joint venture could be proved, the applicants could not show the connection between the venture and the infringements without the use of the emails: at [32]. Given their inadmissibility, the third, fourth and fifth “essential propositions” could not be sustained. Therefore the appeal was upheld in favour of the respondents.

The High Court Decision

The High Court (French CJ, Crennan, Kiefel, Gageler and Keane JJ) unanimously dismissed the appeal, adopting in whole the reasoning of the Full Court of the Federal Court: at [33]-[36]. The crux of the court's decision rests on the fact that while the trial judge did not use the word “tendency” at any stage to describe the use to which the email evidence was put, “nor refer to s 97 of the Evidence Act his Honour, as already pointed out, used the email evidence in such a way as to justify the Full Court's view of his reasoning process.” (at [35]). In the court's view, the applications did not involve a question of law or an issue of public importance, and as the opinion the Full Court of the Federal Court took of the evidence was reasonably open to it, the application for special leave to appeal the decision was dismissed.

Conclusion

The decision, though brief, does enunciate an important rule in construing and applying the tendency evidence rule under s 97 of the Evidence Act 1995 (Cth). This is that, where evidence is adduced under a specific head, for a specific purpose, the court will nonetheless look to the substance of the way in which the evidence was actually used in order to ascertain whether or not it was done so correctly. This involves a three-stage test. The first stage is to ask “under what section of the Evidence Act was the evidence adduced?” The second stage is to look at how the evidence was used, and whether it accords with that section. If not, then determine what section it does come under and apply the rules under that section. This should alert practitioners to the need to be careful of how they use the evidence they adduce in court, even in the civil context, and that the courts will look to the substance of its use and not simply to its form.

Sunday 26 May 2013

Wallace v Kam [2013] HCA 19

While I was in the middle of studying for my most recent post-grad course on medical law, the High Court of Australia published its ruling in the case of Wallace v Kam. While only a short judgement, it has set down the law with respect to a medical practitioner's duty to warn of material risks to their patients, in light of the provisions of the Civil Liability Act 2002 (NSW).


The recent decision by the High Court of Australia in Wallace v Kam [2013] HCA 19 clarifies the position of medical practitioners in failing to disclose material risks to patients, in situations where an injury unrelated to an undisclosed risk materialises.

Background

Mr Wallace was treated for a condition of his lumbar spine by Dr Kam, a neurosurgeon, who failed to warm him of two inherent risks in a surgical procedure. One was temporary damage to nerves in his thighs, known as ‘bilateral femoral neurapraxia. The second was a 5% chance of “permanent and catastrophic paralysis resulting from damage to his spinal nerves (at [1]). The surgery was unsuccessful, and in addition, Mr Wallace unfortunately sustained neurapraxia. He did, however, avoid the risk of paralysis.

Mr Wallace claimed damages for the neurapraxia, alleging Dr Kam negligently failed to warn him of either risk, and that had he been so warned of either or both, he would not have undergone the surgery.

Harrison J dismissed the claim, finding that even if Mr Wallace had been warned of the risk of neurapraxia, he would have gone ahead with the surgery regardless. His Honour declined to make any finding regarding the risk of paralysis on the grounds that “legal cause” of Mr Wallace’s neurapraxia, “could never be the failure to warn of some other risk that did not materialise” (Wallace v Ramsay Health Care Ltd [2010] NSWSC 518 at [96]).

Mr Wallace appealed to the NSW Court of Appeal where Allsop P and Basten JJA dismissed the appeal on basis that a doctor should not be held liable for a harm that did not directly arise from the alleged breach of duty (Wallace v Kam [2012] NSWCA 82 at [18] (per Allsop P) and [173] (per Basten JA)). Beazley JA dissented on the basis that the risk of paralysis was one that Mr Wallace would not have borne had he been properly informed. The risk was not of the kind mooted by Gummow J in Chappel v Hart [1998] HCA 55 at [66], where his Honour considered the hypothetical situation of Mrs Hart suffering injury through the misapplication of anaesthetic; a risk completely unrelated to Dr Chappel’s duty to inform her of material risks. The risk of neurapraxia and the risk of paralysis were both material risks Dr Kam had a duty to warn Mr Wallace about. In the hypothetical of Gummow J, the harm and the duty owed are unrelated; in the case of Mr Wallace though, the Dr Kam breached his duty to inform, and as a direct result Mr Wallace suffered harm.

The High Court Decision

The High Court (French CJ, Crennan, Kiefel, Gageler and Keane JJ) unanimously upheld the decision of the NSW Court of Appeal, dismissing Mr Wallace’s appeal.

The court restated the common law duty of medical practitioners established in Rogers v Whitaker (1992) 175 CLR 479 as being to “warn the patient of “material risks” of physical injury inherent in a proposed treatment” (at [8]). However, the court held that the damage suffered by the patient was not an impairment of their “right to choose”, nor exposure to an “undisclosed risk” (at [9]). Rather, the damage is, limited to the physical harm sustained by the patient in undergoing the procedure (at [9]). In other words, the patient must sustain physical injury in order for the failure to warn to be actionable. The question therefore, is whether the harm sustained must be the one the medical practitioner failed to warn of. Such a question leads to considerations of causation where the harm sustained is not a material risk that was not disclosed.

The court considered that the issue of causation involved two questions: how the particular harm occurred; and a “normative question as to whether legal responsibility for that particular harm occurring in that way should be attributed to a particular person.” (at [11]). While under the common law, these two questions had often been subsumed under the language of “directness” and “proximity”, the statutory requirements under the Civil Liability Act 2002 (NSW), s 5D, made these two questions distinct, being ss 5D(1)(a) and 5D(1)(b) respectively. The answer to the first question is an entirely factual one: was negligence a necessary condition of the harm suffered? (at [14]). In the case of a medical practitioner failing to exercise reasonable care and skill in warning a patient of material risks, the factual question is to be determined by s 5D(3), “If it is relevant to the determination of factual causation to determine what the person who suffered harm would have done if the negligent person had not been negligent: (a) the matter is to be determined subjectively in the light of all relevant circumstances”. The second, normative, question is whether it is appropriate for the scope of the negligent person’s liability to extend to the harm (at [14]). This is to be answered in accordance with s 5D(4) that states, “For the purpose of determining the scope of liability, the court is to consider (amongst other relevant things) whether or not and why responsibility for the harm should be imposed on the negligent party.”

In assessing the statutory tests, the court concluded that in reality they simply restated the common law. Therefore, the factual test under s 5D(1)(a) is “nothing more or less” than the “but for” test: on the balance of probabilities, would the harm that occurred not have occurred but for the negligence alleged? (at [16]). Under the s 5D(1)(b) test, the court considered that the cases will fall into one of two categories: an established class; and novel cases. Those falling into the established class will be answered by the application of precedent; “appropriate” is determined by reference to the limits of the duty to inform at common law. The novel class is answered through the application of s 5D(4): “What is required in such a case is the identification and articulation of an evaluative judgment by reference to “the purposes and policy of the relevant part of the law”” (at [23]).

In the case of a failure to warn of a material risk that does not materialise, but nonetheless a patient suffers an injury as a result of agreeing to the procedure, the court held that there was a limiting principle, being, “the scope of liability in negligence normally does not extend beyond liability for the occurrence of such harm the risk of which it was the duty of the negligent party to exercise reasonable care and skill to avoid.” (at [24]). The court cited with approval the decision of the House of Lords in Banque Bruxelles Lambert SA v Eagle Star Insurance Co Ltd [1997] AC 191, where, at 213, it held that a person is only responsible for the consequences of the information they provided being wrong; not all the consequences of a particular course of action a person may embark upon as a result of that information. The rationale given for this principle was that the elements of duty and causation of damage in negligence serve different functions. The duty of care imposes a “forward-looking rule of conduct” while causation imposes “a backward-looking attribution of responsibility for breach of the rule” (at [26]).

The court drew a distinction though, between cases where an injury occurring is the accumulated risk of several factors, and separate and distinct possible harms (at [34] and [36]). In the former, a failure to warn of one of the risk factors, which if known would lead to the patient not consenting to a procedure, will render the medical practitioner liable. In the latter case however, the potential harms are unrelated. Thus the injury is not the consequence of the lack of information they failed to provide regarding a distinct harm. Such was the finding of the court with regard to Mr Wallace; the risk of paralysis was not a contributing factor to the risk of neurapraxia, and as Mr Wallace was found to be willing to proceed with the procedure if he had known of the risk of neurapraxia, his appeal was ultimately unsuccessful.

Analysis and Conclusions

While the High Court in Wallace v Kam [2013] HCA 19 has reaffirmed the widely held understanding of the law regarding material risks, the reliance on precedent under the ss 5D(1)(a) and 5D(1)(b) tests does not solve the issue illustrated starkly by the differences between its judgment and those of Allsop P and Basten JA of the NSW Court of Appeal on the one hand, and Beazley JA on the other. Indeed, the issue is discussed in the judgment at [26], where their Honours note that while the “consequences of negligence is often coextensive with the content of the duty of the negligent party” it “is not always so coextensive.” The problem arises insofar as the court accepted that because the duty of care is forward looking and causation of damage is backwards looking, the “policy considerations” informing each may be different. But, this begs the question as to how the duty of care is to be enforced if the only means by which it can be enforced is not considered to be coextensive? There is no doubt that Dr Kam failed to warn Mr Wallace of the risk of paralysis, but should Dr Kam therefore be able to breach this duty with impunity simply because it was another harm that eventuated? Such was inherent in the reasoning of Beazley JA (Wallace v Kam [2012] NSWCA 82 at [136]-[151]). In her Honour’s view, “the causation question has to be determined having regard to the content of the duty, namely a duty to warn of material risks.” (at [148]). That being said, the passages cited in support of this view (at [147]) from Rosenberg v Percival [2001] HCA 18 at [86] (per Gummow J) refers to “that risk” in regard to a risk not warned of eventuating, not to a different risk. The other passages her Honour cites from Chappel v Hart [1998] HCA 55 at [7] (per Gaudron J) and [65] (per Gummow J) simply state the content of the duty to warn, not how it relates to the coextensive duty of causation. While the foregoing may address precedential issues, does not address the logical ones that are at the core of Beazley JA’s judgment as to ability to enforce the duty, which remain unanswered. Nonetheless, we now have a clear ratio as to the state of the law with regard to a failure to warn of material risks that do not eventuate, but where injury occurs otherwise. While this may set at ease the minds of medical practitioners and lawyers, it will do little to assuage the worries of patients in future who may be in a similar position to Mr Wallace.

Quasi-Contract and Restitution: The Case of Sumpter v Hedges

The following essay discusses the history and rationale underpinning the case of Sumpter v Hedges, a classic case in the field of quasi-contract and thus now restitution. It is useful to those seeking to gain an understanding of this rather difficult area of law and the problems inherent in it.(This essay was previously published by myself on a different blog some while back, simply because I was a little bit proud of it. I republish it here by way of introduction to my new blog)

Quasi-Contract and Restitution: The Case of Sumpter v Hedges

The case of Sumpter v Hedges1 is notable for the quasi-contractual principle it enunciated that 'the circumstances must be such as to give an option to the defendant to take or not to take the benefit of the work done' for an action for a quantum meruit to be successful. It is an exemplar of what has become known as the principle of free acceptance. Yet despite its adoption in subsequent case law as good authority, Sumpter and the principle of free acceptance raise considerable conceptual problems in terms of unjust enrichment. How well does the null hypothesis of a defendant being able to reject a benefit sit with the concepts of benefit, fault, or even under the rubric of unjust enrichment? How much authority should be given to a case decided within the ambit of quasi-contract and, given the historical forms of pleading, was it decided correctly then? This essay will address these questions through an analysis of Sumpter. It will reconsider the decision in Sumpter and determine whether or not it is correct in light of the law at the time and our understanding of it. It will argue the decision in Sumpter is correct but not on the basis of free acceptance; that the forms of pleading distorted the view of the rationale underpinning the restitutionary principles present within quasi-contract and that modern understanding of the law of restitution can serve as illustrative in so contending.

Quasi-Contract

The theory of quasi-contract was of an obligation created by an implied promise, whether it was for a sum of money or a service to be rendered. It was a wholly fictional promise which could arise out of a genuine one or the surrounding circumstances and framed as such within the historical forms of pleading which required a plaintiff to sue in indebitatus assumpsit for money had and received, and/or quantum meruit.2 As Ibbetson outlines, an action in indebitatus assumpsit for money had and received 'came to be used as a contractual action in the early years of the sixteenth century.3 It was an action analogous in purpose to the recovery of a debt, and based on 'a promise made subsequent to the creation of the debt and logically separate from it.4' Its purpose was to simply allow a plaintiff to use a separate form of action from assumpsit, as being formally an action on the case, it could not be used 'if an action of debt was available in the same cause of action.'5 It created no new liability nor was any further consideration required and, based as it was on the subsequent promise, 'did not in any way depend on the debt which lay at the root of it having grown out of any contract.'6 It arose from the circumstances which rendered the retention of money by a defendant as being unjust.7 During the course of its development in the sixteenth century, the courts came to require no proof of this promise and by the seventeenth it could be said that indebitatus assumpsit rested on an implied promise, though one that was understood as wholly fictional.8 Quantum meruit, deriving from the Latin “what one has earned”, was just that. It was neither a debt, nor resting upon a fictional promise. Rather it was based on an actual agreement to pay a reasonable sum for services performed.9 It was a request made by a defendant which could be directly inferred from circumstances, and one which could be said to rest on a true implied contract.10 As Winfield notes, these cases were based on true contracts, in which case, it was quite right to assert they are firmly rooted in many of the doctrines and principles of contract law.11

The developments of these two conceptually distinct, though related actions over the following centuries led to them both becoming incorporated into what we have come to know as quasi-contract. The first was that a plaintiff was allowed to recover on a quantum meruit basis in an indebitatus assumpsit action where an agreement to pay a fixed sum could not be ascertained.12 The second were a minority of cases not easily justifiable as being decided on the basis of an implied contract between the parties.13 As Barton notes, if a plaintiff who, contracting to do one thing does another, seeks a quantum meruit for the work done, it cannot arise from a promise implied from the circumstances, but rather 'upon the defendant's obligation, arising from the equity of the case rather than from his consent, to pay for the benefit which he has received.'14 Ibbetson identifies two conclusions which subsequently arose, the first being that an action for a quantum meruit was one in indebitatus assumpsit, rather than that damages in the latter could be assessed on a quantum meruit where there was found to be a promise, but not one with a fixed sum.15 The second, that all actions to recover a quantum meruit were based on an implied contract rather than most being decided on this basis while others on restitutionary grounds.16 The union which occurred between both is obvious when considering that plaintiffs could sue on an indebitatus assumpsit count for a quantum meruit, and the courts now had to consider what would otherwise have been cases on a quantum meruit count, within the form of action of indebitatus assumpsit and which would become known as quasi-contract.

The conceptual issues arising from this fusion of both actions into quasi-contract led to a variety of questions concerning its principles and rationales which were never sufficiently addressed. Hunter and Carter note the issues concerning the very nature of an implied promise by asking whether it was genuine, though tacit, or one imposed by the circumstances?17 These very questions harken back to the distinctions between the old forms of indebitatus assumpsit and quantum meruit discussed. Indeed, the development of the principles within quasi-contract and their application within Sumpter v Hedges illustrate these tensions.

Acceptance

The concept of free acceptance was defined by Birks as being that acceptance 'occurs where a recipient knows that a benefit is being offered to him non-gratuitously and where he, having the opportunity to reject, elects to accept,'18 a view which is in accordance with the definition of a quasi-contract advance by Latham CJ in Steele v Tardiani.19 Acceptance is assessed subjectively and serves as a basis for unjust enrichment on subjective acceptance and it being unjust to accept a benefit with knowledge it was not gratuitous. It is the subjective aspect of free acceptance though, which has had a deleterious impact on plaintiffs' claims. Sumper is the classic example, where the English Court of Appeal upheld the trial judge's ruling the builder could only recover for the value of the loose materials but not the work unpaid for, nor on a quantum meruit for the work performed. Collins LJ stated the view of the court that where the work was done on land, and there is no option provided to the defendant of accepting or rejecting the benefit, the recourse must be had to other facts to 'ground the inference of a new contract.20 There are two primary justifications as to why free acceptance ruled the quasi-contractual world. The first is it served to protect defendants from claims as to an objective but unrequested benefit being conferred upon them which they could be compelled to repay. This recalls the rationale of indebitatus assumpsit discussed above, that considered whether it was just in the circumstances for a plaintiff to be compensated. The second goes to the characterisation of quasi-contract as an agreement arising between the parties which, but for the failure or non-compliance with some other requirement, formed a binding promise between them. It was an implied contract by operation of law recognising a subjective agreement had arisen. It reflects the rationale underlying the old quantum meruit count: the ability to reject served as proof of acceptance in circumstances where often times explicit acceptance, which could have given rise to an actual contract, was not present.

While Sumpter correctly stated the principle of free acceptance, it is debatable as to whether the principle was correctly applied or rather the result of an historical anachronism borne out of pleading within the form of indebitatus assumpsit and the merging of principles which took place via a quantum meruit being claimed under it. This contention is supported by the judgements as to there being no circumstances which could have given rise to a new contract, and neither could any claim be brought concerning work done under the abandoned contract. Chitty LJ invoked the rule in Cutter v Powell21 that a plaintiff could not sue on a quantum meruit for work performed if there is a subsisting contract which set out the renumeration on terms for that work. The rationale underlying the rule is that, if I have contracted with you to perform a service on particular terms, then I cannot claim you should pay me for that same work on different terms without showing an agreement to that effect. In Sumpter then, the plaintiff would have been required to show that, after the contract had been abandoned, a new agreement arose whereupon the defendant accepted the incomplete work on the terms of providing reasonable renumeration for it. Failing the null hypothesis of not being free to reject, such an agreement was impossible to infer. As the abandoned contract was on different terms, it could not show acceptance of the work even though logically the construction of whole buildings would, by necessity, require the partial construction of buildings along the way to completion.22 In a sense, the decision asks us to adopt a kind of fiction: that under an entire contract, a building does not exist until it is finished, as though where one minute there is no building the next a whole one appears. Conceptually, this reflects the idea of quasi-contract expressed above which was based upon there being an actual agreement; not one arising by operation of law but rather simply one recognised by law. Therefore, within the rationale underpinning the old indebitatus assumpsit count it is necessary to ask whether it is, in reality, just and correct for a defendant to retain an objective benefit where a request has been made under a contract which would obviate any concerns as to injustice arising by forcing a defendant to pay for that benefit.

Benefit

Benefit, in quasi-contract may be either subjective or incontrovertible (regarding to money, being no reasonable person could deny a benefit).23 The subjective test of benefit is one predicated on that of free acceptance, and has served as an efficient way for courts to circumnavigate the question of whether a defendant has been enriched. If something has been requested by a defendant it must be of benefit to them, it is not for the court to inquire. Recognising outside of money that courts only had recourse to a narrow, subjective test which could result in a variety of injustices, the case of Craven-Ellis v Canons Ltd24 has come to be recognised as broadening the concept of incontrovertible benefit, the rationale underlying which went towards a consideration of the circumstances. Greer LJ held the defendant's argument was invalid where it sought to assert it should not be liable to pay for services which were a necessary expenditure; they 'would have had to get some other agent' to perform them.25 The issue arose again in the case of Greenwood v Bennett26 where Lord Denning MR based his view on the objective benefit the defendant received and the absence of risk assumed by the plaintiff. He considered whether a defendant had been benefited by repairs done to the plaintiff's stolen car (of which he was completely innocent) so as to enable the plaintiff to have a direct cause of action against the defendant. Central to his reasoning was that the plaintiff did not assume a risk he would be deprived of the fruits of his labour, and despite not being free to reject the work, a greater injustice would result if the plaintiff were not entitled to recover, especially if doing so resulted in no injustice being done to the defendant, in terms of burdening them with a prohibitive cost. Neither decision rests on acceptance, but a combination of benefit and fault, the former assessed on an objective basis. In this sense, the reasoning in Craven-Ellis and of Lord Denning MR in Greenwood, illustrate a different formulation of assessing unjust enrichment than in Sumpter, and is more consistent with the “Bargain-for-Benefit” test advanced by Burrows. Burrows, rejecting Birks' free acceptance as the basis for assessing benefit, proffering that evidence of actual receipt of an objective benefit–being something realisable in money–was required.27 Once that objective benefit was found, any recourse to subjective devaluation could be rebutted if it was shown the defendant 'bargained-for' the objective benefit `thereby manifesting a positive desire, and willingness to pay for it'.28 On this formulation, while the factual basis of the claim rests in a failed or terminated contract, the rationale is different to one requiring there be evidence of a new, separate agreement. Of note though, is absent request in Craven-Ellis and Greenwood there is no role to play for subjective devaluation or a bargain for the benefit. However, this is resolvable by recourse to the rationale underlying free acceptance. Free acceptance is not simply a ground for unjust enrichment, but a test. In Birks' formulation, it prevents recourse to subjective devaluation for, as noted above, if the defendant has accepted then it must be beneficial and it would be unjust for the defendant to deny enrichment. In other words, in looking towards whether something is a benefit a test is to see if it is subjectively valuable, but logically this cannot exclude objective value, only operate where it is in doubt. Returning to Sumpter, a mistake was made in holding that absent subjective benefit, there is no benefit. This cannot marry in a system which recognises there are incontrovertible benefits, even if limited to money. It illustrates a failing of the application of the law in the context of asking whether it is unjust for a defendant to retain a benefit in the circumstances. However, in the context of a contractual agreement, such rationale makes perfect sense if one were to remove from consideration the whole context of the original building contract. Absent any law of restitution, all the court need ask is whether a contract arose between the parties that was unenforceable for not complying with some prescribed requirement. If so, then it is a valid quasi-contract. If not; if no such agreement had been made–no offer, no acceptance–then how could the defendant be liable? If though, we turn to an analysis based upon benefit, that request or acceptance goes to the gratuity of the work (or risk taken), then we are left with a benefit which cannot be subjectively devalued. Returning to Craven-Ellis and Greenwood, there were measurable objective or incontrovertible benefits. No recourse was necessary to free acceptance, as benefit was not in doubt and therefore did not require assessment. In terms of subjective devaluation, the fact it was incontrovertible addresses this also, in which case, subjective devaluation is not synonymous with free acceptance, but a requirement which free acceptance is also a test for. For example, I cannot subjectively devalue money, services I require, a car I wanted repaired, or building work I wanted performed. Outside the context of a contract, it would be contrary to the rationale of indebitatus assumpsit to contend, I did not want this building because I wanted more of it done. The subjective devaluation of free acceptance would only serve to contextualise the benefit received as to the renumeration due, but not to its existence as being owed.

Fault

There is an issue in Sumpter as to what role did fault play? Collins LJ noted the case may have had a different result had the plaintiff 'merely broken his contract in some way so as not to give the defendant the right to treat him as having abandoned' it. It is difficult to follow why some lesser breach would have given the plaintiff a right to a quantum meruit in light of the preceding discussion. However it does raise an issue of fault and there are cases involving where a plaintiff not in breach has recovered on a quantum meruit, yet free acceptance could not apply. The first is Planche v Colburn29 where Tindal CJ awarded the value of the work under a contract to author a manuscript, even though the publisher had not received any part of it, as it had been abandoned by the publisher and no new contract had arisen which allowed the defendant to require production of the work for a different use. The plaintiff was successful even though the defendant had received no benefit and thus, could neither accept nor reject. There was no new special contract, nor was the original one still in existence and open. The rationale advanced by Jones in terms of benefit was that 'The publisher had gained a benefit, for which he had to pay a reasonable sum, because he had bargained for and obtained the writing of the manuscript'.30 Birks has explained the result in terms of 'limited acceptance' whereby sufficient acts of part performance would prevent a defendant from having recourse to subjective devaluation when, through the actions of the defendant the plaintiff is prevented from performing the whole agreement.31 The second case of De Barnardy v Harding32 concerned an agreement to advertise the sale of tickets for seating to view a funeral. After the plaintiff had incurred expenses, but before any tickets were sold, the defendant requested them not to sell any tickets as he would do so himself. Accordingly, the plaintiff forwarded all applicants for tickets to him. The plaintiff sent a bill to the defendant for all of the work done and expenses incurred. The defendant paid for the expenses but refused to pay for the work. Planche v Colburn was stated as authority for the decision 'the defendant having refused to perform his part of the contract, the plaintiff was entitled to treat it as rescinded, and sue on a quantum meruit.' Though there was no question of fault relating to the original contract, having been abandoned by mutual consent, there was in relation to the new agreement insofar as it was implied the plaintiff should recover for the work done as it was at the request of the defendant the old agreement be abandoned.

The applicability of fault is clarified by reference to US jurisprudence. Hunter and Carter, assessing whether the contract should set a ceiling on the amount of recovery under a claim for restitution, discuss the US majority position it should not.33 Inherent in these decisions is the notion that 'because the breaching party forfeits [their] rights under the contract by reason of the breach' they should not have recourse to the price in limiting a plaintiff's recovery. Why on principle which party breaches should determine the level of recovery is problematic. The parties have agreed to price in the context of their risk allocation. To ignore that would be to ignore the agreement regardless of fault in its breach. Furthermore, the point is often raised in regard to unprofitable agreements of a plaintiff suing in restitution in order to obtain a higher sum. Indeed, on Birks' 'limited acceptance' test there is no reason why, if a plaintiff can claim under part performance in restitution, they cannot claim for full performance. It is also difficult to see in Sumpter how the defendant being in breach could have constituted acceptance of the work if that acceptance rested upon a new agreement and, putting to one side any contractual actions which might have accrued, the defendant would still have not been free to reject the work. An explanation must relate to consideration of unjust enrichment which countenances a concept of fault. Had the agreement in Planche been found to be void or unenforceable contractually, and if the author refused to hand in the manuscript, then should he have still recovered on a quantum meruit? According to the court there was a benefit conferred and therefore why should it not, in principle, be remunerated? There was also no benefit to the defendant in De Barnardy and no acceptance of the work. The judgements indicate the sole reason why a claim could not be brought under the contract was that it only provided for a share of profits and not work done. As no profits were realised and the work done under the contract went with it, where is the implied agreement? If however, these decisions are viewed through the prism of fault, there arises a coherent explanation. It is best akin to the equitable maxim that “he who seeks equity must do equity” and there is little reason why such principles should not be looked at in explaining decisions based on an action that, as the old indebitatus assumpsit action for money had and received was formulated, asks the question of whether it would be just for the defendant to retain the benefit. In Sumpter, as it was not the defendant who abandoned the contract, and as they were not free to accept the work, was it unjust for them to retain it unpaid? No, they did not force the plaintiff to abandon the work, as neither would someone receiving a gratuitous benefit be accused of forcing the other to offer it as such. There is a case on the preceding discussion under acceptance and benefit that the plaintiff should still be entitled to some form of quantum meruit considering the justness of the situation, but that is not to say any restitution made should not be done without the plaintiff's abandonment in mind. That being said, it is important to note that quasi-contract does have within it a fault element. It would be troubling if any principle which has the term “unjust” within it did not.

Conclusion

The historical development of indebitatus assumpsit for money had and received and quantum meruit led to a theory of quasi-contract that contained cases explainable by references to implied, but actual agreements, and those which were properly resitutionary. The result are cases such as Planche, De Barnardy, Craven-Ellis, and Sumpter. The ill-ease with which these cases sit with one another is obvious and the cause is this melding. If this is not evidence of the application of inconsistent principles, it is difficult to conceive of what is. Examining those principles in Sumpter have illustrated this inconsistency, and the explanation proffered here has sought to reconcile them with historical and doctrinal bases. If Sumpter is correct then the other cases are wrong, yet courts have continued to apply them. The converse could be said but for the fact the principles stated in Sumpter were entirely correct; it was their subsequent application which was flawed and it is on this basis it should be understood. There is some evidence that it is, with the courts moving towards an objective assessment of benefit which must, by necessity, put free acceptance into its proper theoretical context. Likewise, the movement of the law towards a remedial model will allow a greater role for the concept of fault in unjust enrichment separate from contract. That being said, this essay has shown that such developments will find an amiable basis within those decisions made in the era of quasi-contract and are therefore ones which will continue to serve it well in the future development of the law of restitution.

1[1898] 1 QB 673.
2D. Ibbetson, 'Implied Contracts and Restitution: History in the High Court of Australia' (1988) 8 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 313.
3Id at 314.
4Ibid.
5Ibid.
6Ibid.
7NSW Law Reform Commission, Community Law Reform Program: Eleventh Report - Restitution Of Benefits Conferred Under Mistake Of Law Report No 53 (1987) [http://www.lawlink.nsw.gov.au/lrc.nsf/pages/R53CHP2].
8Ibbetson at 314.
9Ibid.
10Id at 315.
11P.H. Winfield, The Province of the Law of Tort (1931) at 159 cited in Ibid.
12Ibbetson at 316.
13Id at 316.
14J.L. Barton, 'Contract and Quantum Meruit: The Antecedents of Cutter v Powel', (1987) 8 Jnl Legal History 48 at 58.
15Ibbetson at 316.
16Ibid.
17H.O. Hunter and J.W. Carter, 'Quantum Meruit and Building Contracts – Part I' (1989) 2 JCL 95 at 96.
18P. Birks, An Introduction to the Law of Restitution, (1989) at 265; J.G. Tolhurst and J.W. Carter, 'Acceptance of Benefit as a Basis for Restitution' (2002) 18 JCL 52 at 53.
19(1946) 72 CLR 386 at 393.
20Id at [676].
21(1795) 101 ER 573.
22P. Birks, `In Defence of Free Acceptance' in A Burrows (ed), Essays on the Law of Restitution (1991) at 140; P. Birks, An Introduction to the Law of Restitution (1989) at 233.
23J.W. Carter, E. Peden & G. Tolhurst, Contract Law in Australia (5th ed, 2007) at [38-10]-[38-13].
24[1936] KB 403.
25Id at 412.
26 [1973] 1 Q.B. 195 (C.A.).
27A. Burrows, `Free Acceptance and the Law of Restitution' (1988) 104 LQR 576.
28A. Burrows, The Law of Restitution (1993) at 12.
29(131) 8 Bing 14, 131 ER 305, 5 Carr & P 58, 172 ER 876.
30G. Jones, 'Claims Arising Out of Contracts Which Do Not Materialize' (1979-1980) 18 U. W. Ontario L. Rev. 447 at 458.
31P. Birks, (1989) at 126-7; J.W. Carter, 'Discharged Contracts: Claims for Restitution' (1997) 11 JCL 130 at 140.
32(1853) 8 Ex 822, 155 ER 1586.
33H.O. Hunter & J.W. Carter, 'Quantum Meruit and Building Contracts–Part II' (1989) 2 JCL 189 at 191.